Reasonable Humans and Animals
Also here: “Reasonable Humans and Animals,” John Simmons: In 3 page PDF.
Also here: “Reasonable Humans and Animals,” John Simmons: In 3 page PDF.
John Simmons, Ph.D.
Philosophy Department, Addison College,
NH
“It is easy for us to criticize the
prejudices of our grandfathers, from which our fathers freed themselves. It is
more difficult to distance ourselves from our own views, so that we can
dispassionately search for prejudices among the beliefs and values we hold.” - Peter Singer
“It's a matter of taking the side of the weak against
the strong, something the best people have always done.” - Harriet Beecher Stowe
In my 8 or
so years experience of teaching philosophy, ethics and logic courses, I have
found that no topic brings out the rational and emotional best and worst in people
than ethical questions about the treatment of animals. This is not surprising
since, unlike questions about social policy and about what other people should do, moral questions about animals are personal. As philosopher Peter Singer
has observed, “For most human beings, especially in modern urban and suburban
communities, the most direct form of contact with non-human animals is at
mealtimes: we eat them.”[1]
For most of us, then, our own behavior is challenged when we reflect on the
reasons given to think that change is needed in our treatment of, and attitudes
toward, animals. That the issue is personal presents unique challenges, and
great opportunities, for intellectual and moral progress.
Here I present some of the reasons given for and against taking animals
seriously and reflect on the role of reason in our lives. I examine the common
assumption that there is nothing wrong
with harming animals -- causing them pain, suffering, and an early death – so
they might be eaten. We will see if moral “common sense” in this area can
survive critical scrutiny. Our method, useful for better understanding all
ethical debates, is to identify unambiguous and precise moral conclusions and make all the reasons in favor of the
conclusion explicit, leaving no assumption unstated.
Harms and Reasons
Why is the treatment of animals a moral issue? Plutarch suggested an
answer nearly two thousand years ago when he reflected on the killing of
animals for food:
But for the sake of some little mouthful of flesh we
deprive a soul of the sun and light, and of that proportion of life and time it
had been born into the world to enjoy.
The simple answer is that animals are harmed by the practices required to bring them to our plates, and
harms need rational defense. Chickens, pigs, cows, and other animals are
conscious, can feel pleasure and pain, and their lives can go better or worse,
from their own point of view. Raising and killing them is bad for them: they experience pain, suffering, deprivation, boredom
and an early death. Everything is
taken from them so that they might be eaten. And this is true regardless of the
conditions they are raised in.
Let us consider the common view
that, even though it’s true that animals are harmed (indeed greatly harmed) by the practices
required for meat eating, these practices
are morally permissible nevertheless. We will see that common arguments for
this perspective all have premises that are either false or in need of serious
defense. The methods used in responding to these arguments will prove useful
for addressing further arguments and objections beyond those discussed here.
Defending Tradition
One of the first things said is that it’s not wrong to harm animals for
food because it’s a “tradition”: it’s something we do, and have done, for a
long time. True, for many people, eating animals is a tradition. But not all traditions are good or right: the
important question is always whether an aspect of a tradition can be supported
by good moral reasons or not. Also, for many people, eating animals is not a tradition: for thousands of years
there have been people who extend their compassion to animals, and many other
people who were raised eating animals start new traditions when they see that
consistency and moral reasoning demands change.
Second, some people say that it’s “natural” to raise and kill animals
to eat them, so it’s right. But the meaning of “natural” is extremely obscure:
people can mean very different things when they use the term. Whatever meaning
one uses, however, it’s very hard to see how modern, industrial methods of
factory farming, transport and slaughter are at all “natural.” It’s not even
clear how an individual’s raising and killing, say, a pig or a chicken in her
backyard would be “natural” either.
But the relationship between what’s “natural,” in any sense of the term, and what’s morally right does not help this
argument. Selfishness and cruelty are often quite “natural,” but they are not
right or good. Walking on one’s hands is a quite “unnatural” way to transport
oneself, but it’s usually not wrong to do so. Some “natural” behaviors are right, but many are deeply wrong,
and advocates of this argument forget that simple point. Whether something is “natural” or not is
irrelevant to its morality.
Third, some people insist that it’s nutritionally
necessary to eat meat, milk and eggs and, therefore, it’s right that
animals are raised and killed to be eaten. But this argument ignores common
sense and disrespects medical science. If it were true that we have to eat meat and other animal
products, then there would be no people who abstain from doing do so because
they would all be dead. But there are such people, alive and well, and medical
science supplements common observations with evidence to show that they are
often healthier than omnivores.[2] Consider the position
statement of the leading authority on nutrition in North
America based on their seventeen-page review of the recent
nutrition research:
It is the position of the
American Dietetic Association and Dietitians of Canada that appropriately planned
vegetarian diets are healthful, nutritionally adequate, and provide health
benefits in the prevention and treatment of certain diseases. . . Well-planned vegan and
other types of vegetarian diets are appropriate for all stages of the life
cycle, including during pregnancy, lactation, infancy, childhood, and
adolescence. . . A vegetarian, including vegan, diet can meet current
recommendations for all of these nutrients. . . Vegetarian diets offer a number
of nutritional benefits, including lower levels of saturated fat, cholesterol,
and animal protein as well as higher levels of carbohydrates, fiber, magnesium,
potassium, folate, and antioxidants such as vitamins C and E and
phytochemicals. Vegetarians have been reported to have lower body mass indices
than nonvegetarians, as well as lower rates of death from ischemic heart
disease; vegetarians also show lower blood cholesterol levels; lower blood
pressure; and lower rates of hypertension, type 2 diabetes, and prostate and
colon cancer.[3]
So this defense of eating animals is either ignorant of, or
disrespectful towards, the huge (and growing) body of research that shows the
health benefits from eating a diet based on vegetables, legumes, fruits and
whole grains, and ignores the growing literature detailing the variety of harms
for humans that can result from the production and consumption of animal
products.[4]
This argument thus has a false empirical premise: it is not supported by
science and medical research.
A pattern is emerging, and we can use it to make a point about how to
critically respond to reasoning given in ethics. There are two useful critical
ways to respond to moral arguments: an “Oh yeah?” response, and a “So what?”
response. The former “Oh yeah?” response denies the truth of the premise and
the latter “So what?” response denies the truth of the (often unstated)
assumption needed to validly reach the conclusion. We can see these helpful
responses in action by considering more arguments in favor of harming animals.
A fourth argument is based in the claim that “meat tastes good” or that
it is pleasurable to eat it. But so what?
Just because something causes pleasure doesn’t make it right. We do not think
that pleasures automatically justify
harming humans: if things are
different in the animal case, we need reasons to see why this would be so. And,
besides, there are many other pleasure-producing cuisines (often they are
ethnic) to choose from that aren’t based on animal products anyway.
A fifth argument is based on someone’s claiming that he or she “just
couldn’t give up meat or dairy products or eggs.” Oh yeah? Since so many other people have given these up, or never
ate them in the first place, this claim is likely disingenuous. And since this
person probably hasn’t even tried changing his or her diet for moral reasons,
he or she likely lacks the evidence needed to confidently make that judgment.
Sixth, people claim that animals eat other animals, so it’s right for
us to do. Oh yeah? Only some animals eat other animals, and
these are not chickens, pigs or cows. And so
what? Many animals do lots of things that we wouldn’t want to do, and
should not do (e.g., eat their own excrement and, sometimes, their young), so
why should we imitate animals in only some ways, but not others? A principled response is needed for this
argument to have any force.
Sometimes people say that we are
animals, thinking that this justifies our killing and eating animals. But it
does not: just because we are animals
does not mean that it’s morally right for us to do all the other things that other animals do; above we saw many
things that (some) animals do that would be wrong for us to do. And if we are
animals, we are unique animals with the ability to reason about the morality of
our actions, in light of their consequences for others. Should not we use this
reason to do what reduces harms to animals and ourselves?
Seventh, people say eating meat is “convenient.” Oh yeah? Many meat-based dishes are inconvenient to prepare, and plant-based dishes are usually as convenient as eating meat anyway.
It’s just a matter of choosing something else from the same menu or same
grocery store. But since doing the right thing sometimes requires our being inconvenienced in minor (and sometimes
major) ways, so what?
Eighth, it is sometimes said that we have a right to treat animals these ways, and that animals have no rights to not be treated these ways.
That might be true, but reasonable people want reasons for why they should think that. First, they will want to
know what “right” is under consideration. Suppose it’s the right to not be caused to suffer and die for someone else’s
pleasure. Is it because animals don’t do math problems, write novels or
make moral decisions that they don’t have this right? If so, since babies and
many other humans don’t (and, for some, can’t) do these things, this view about
moral rights denies them rights also.
Is it because animals are not biologically
human that they lack the right to not be harmed for others? Interestingly,
nearly all philosophers who have considered these issues reject this kind of
theory: on their views, the fact that we are biologically human has little to
do with what we are owed, morally. This hypothesis is confirmed, in part, by
each of us asking us what it is about
ourselves that, e.g., makes it such
that it would be wrong to cause us pain and kill us. For most people, the
obvious explanation is that this would hurt greatly, we would suffer enormously
and our early deaths would prevent us from experiencing all the good things we
(hopefully) would have experienced. It’s not because of some genes we have or
where we are on some chart in a biology book that explains our moral status;
rather, it is a matter of our vulnerability to physical and/or psychological
harm.
But since many animals are also
vulnerable to such harms, these animals seem to be due the respect due to, at
least, comparably-minded humans.
Since this respect requires not raising and killing these humans for the mere pleasures
of eating them, rational consistency requires the same treatment for
chickens, cows, pigs and other animals who often have far richer mental lives
than many humans.
Farming Facts
These are just a few of the more common arguments given in defense of
raising and killing animals for food. The fact that they are all quite weak
suggests that people’s resistance to change regarding these issues might be
based on non-rational influences, not critical thinking and unbiased inquiry.
But the fact that a strong defense of the status
quo is lacking does not give us yet enough positive reason to think that
animals are treated wrongly. To see these reasons, we must consider in brief
detail how are animals are harmed so that they might be served on our plates.
The treatment of animals in farms and slaughterhouses has been well
documented by all major print and
television media.[5] On both
“factory” and the few remaining “family” farms, baby animals are castrated, branded, ear and tail-docked,
and teeth are pulled, all without (costly) anesthesia. “Veal” calves, the male
by-products of the dairy industry, spend their entire life individually chain
at the neck and confined to narrow stalls too narrow for them to turn around
in. “Broiler” chickens, due to selective breeding and growth-promoting
drugs, are killed at forty five days. Such fast growth causes chickens to
suffer from a number of chronic health problems, including leg disorders and
heart disease. “Layer” hens live a year or more in
cages the size of a filing drawer, seven or more per cage, after which they
routinely are starved for two weeks (“force molted”) to encourage another
laying cycle. Female hogs are housed for four or five years in individual
barred enclosures ("gestation stalls") barely wider than their
bodies, where they are forced to birth litter after litter. Until the recent
“Mad Cow” scare, beef and dairy cattle too weak to stand (“downers”) were
dragged or pushed to their slaughter.[6]
Many people would describe the treatment of animals in
slaughterhouses as simply brutal: the title of a 2001 Washington Post entitled “The Die Piece by Piece: In Overtaxed
Plants, Humane Treatment of Cattle is Often a Battle Lost,” is suggestive of
standard operating procedures in American slaughterhouses; more recent stories
reveal similar inhumane conditions. A 2004 New
York Times story documented workers at a chicken slaughterhouse stomping on chickens, kicking them, and violently
slamming them against floors and walls. Those attentive to the news media see
stories like this all too often.
One hopes that this treatment is not routine, but there are is good
reason to be skeptical of claims that it is not. After all, there are no laws
protecting farmed animals, since they are explicitly
excluded from the Animal Welfare Act. The Act says that, “the term ‘animal’ ...
excludes horses not used for research purposes and other farm animals, such as,
but not limited to, livestock or poultry, used or intended for food.”
Reasonable Ethics
So should we think that the harmful treatment of animals in farms and
slaughterhouses is wrong and should not be supported? This conclusion follows
only when moral principles are
conjoined with facts about animal agribusiness and, perhaps, the fact that we
do not need to eat animal products to survive and thrive.
Fortunately, complex moral thinking is not needed to find plausible
principles to apply to this case. The simple, but powerful, “common sense”
principle that we should avoid inflicting and supporting needless harm is
all that is needed, and is supported by a wide range of theoretical perspectives
– secular and religious – in ethics (in fact, nearly all of them). These
theories urge that we should promote goodness and lessen badness or evil,
respect all beings who are conscious
and sentient (not just those who are “rational”), treat others as we would like
to be treated, and otherwise promoting caring, compassionate, sympathetic,
sensitive and fair attitudes and behavior. All of these theories condemn the
practices of contemporary animal agribusiness.
This is true of both secular and religious moral points of view. About
Christianity, It is very doubtful that Jesus – who advocated compassion, love
and mercy – would support the needless killing of animals for pleasure.
Christian theologians and philosophers have carefully engaged these issues and
have argued that theology, the Bible and critical thinking about God’s will likely
supports such compassion.[7] For
those who insist that God supports killing animals for the pleasure of eating
them, we need to ask them, first, how they might know that and, second, what reasons God would have for advocating
eating animals, especially since it is often nutritional harmful for humans.
Perspectives that deny that we should avoid inflicting needless harm
typically degenerate into infantile “might-makes-right” moral theories or they
falsely imply that it’s only because “rational agents” care about
non-rational beings (humans and animals) that it’s be wrong to harm these
beings. This latter thought is mistaken because it’s wrong to harm these beings
because they can be harmed, not
because harming them would upset us.
Thus, it seems that reasonable humans (all of whom have to eat and can
easily choose animal-free foods; they cannot claim they are “too busy” to
refrain from eating animals or that there are “more important things” to do, so
they therefore must eat animals)
should broaden their serious moral
concern to include conscious, sentient beings who are not human: reasonable
people should not eat animals, since this is what the best moral reasons
support.
One final response to arguments for vegetarianism is a response common
to many arguments about issues that challenge how we live our lives: “People
are going to believe whatever they
want to believe, and people are going to do
whatever they want to do.” It’s important to realize that this response is
lamentable: it’s an evasion of the issues, since it does not engage the
arguments. For this issue, it’s an attempt to avoid rational engagement with
uncomfortable questions about the lives and deaths of, each years, tens of
billions of conscious, feeling beings.
Those who are committed to the value of reason in guiding our beliefs,
attitudes, and even our feelings should discourage this response, and promote
reasonableness in all things, not
just a select few, personally-convenient, topics. They should do this also
because this response is false: people sometimes do change their beliefs and behaviors, and on the basis of good
reasons. This is true about many issues, and confronting ethical issues about
animals can often help us better see this for, and in, ourselves.
“The ultimate measure of a man is not where
he stands in moments of comfort and convenience, but where he stands at times
of challenge and controversy.” - Martin Luther King Jr.
[1] Peter Singer, Animal
Liberation, 3rd Ed. (New
York: HarperCollins Publishers, 2002), p. 95.
[3] “Position of the American Dietetic Association and
Dietitians of Canada:
Vegetarian Diets,” Journal of the
American Dietetic Association, Volume 109, Issue 7, Pages 1266-1282 (July 2009). At http://www.eatright.org/About/Content.aspx?id=8357
[4] Eric Schlosser’s book and film Fast Food Nation vividly portrays the harms done to (immigrant)
workers in slaughterhouses, as does Gail Eisnitz’s Slaughterhouse: The Shocking
Story of Greed, Neglect, and Inhumane Treatment Inside the U.S. Meat Industry.
[5] For reviews of this media coverage, see, among many
other sources, Dawn Animal World News
Watch (www.DawnWatch.com) and Vegan Outreach’s E-newsletter (www.veganoutreach.org/enewsletter).
[6] For documentation and further information, see the
literature produced by Vegan Outreach (www.VeganOutreach.org)
and Compassion Over Killing (www.COK.net and www.TryVeg.com).
[7] See The
Christian Vegetarian Association at www.ChristianVeg.com for an overview of this discussion and
literature.
No comments:
Post a Comment